![]() | A request that this article title be changed to Mono-raise criterion is under discussion. Please do not move this article until the discussion is closed. |
A joint Politics and Economics series |
Social choice and electoral systems |
---|
![]() |
![]() |
In social choice, the negative response,[1][2] perversity,[3] or additional support paradox[4] is a pathological behavior of some voting rules where a candidate loses as a result of having too much support (or wins because of increased opposition). In other words, increasing (decreasing) a candidate's ranking or rating causes that candidate to lose (win), respectively.[4] Electoral systems that do not exhibit perversity are sometimes said to satisfy the monotonicity criterion.[5]
Perversity is often described by social choice theorists as an exceptionally severe kind of electoral pathology,[6] as such rules can have "backwards" responses to voters' opinions, where popularity causes defeat while unpopularity leads to a win.[7] Similar rules treat the well-being of some voters as "less than worthless".[8] These issues have led to constitutional prohibitions on such systems as violating the right to equal and direct suffrage.[9][10] Negative response is often cited as an example of a perverse incentive, as rules with negative response can incentivize politicians to take extreme or unpopular positions in an attempt to shed excess votes.[11]
Most ranked methods (including Borda and all common round-robin rules) satisfy positive response,[5] as do all common rated voting methods (including approval, highest medians, and score).[note 1]
Negative responsiveness occurs in instant-runoff voting (IRV),[12] the single transferable vote,[3] and the two-round system.[11] Some quota-based apportionment methods also violate the rule,[13] as can the randomized Condorcet method in cases of cyclic ties.
The participation criterion is closely-related, but different. While positive responsiveness deals with a voter changing their opinion (or vote), participation deals with situations where a voter choosing to cast a ballot at all has a backwards effect on the election.[13]
It is generally agreed among social choice theorists that a voting method that is susceptible to any type of monotonicity failure suffers from a particularly serious defect.
Since we are trying to describe social welfare and not some sort of illfare, we must assume that the social welfare function is such that the social ordering responds positively to alterations in individual values, or at least not negatively. Hence, if one alternative social state rises or remains still in the ordering of every individual without any other change in those orderings, we expect that it rises, or at least does not fall, in the social ordering.
Since we are trying to describe social welfare and not some sort of illfare, we must assume that the social welfare function is such that the social ordering responds positively to alterations in individual values, or at least not negatively. Hence, if one alternative social state rises or remains still in the ordering of every individual without any other change in those orderings, we expect that it rises, or at least does not fall, in the social ordering.
:4
was invoked but never defined (see the help page).
Cite error: There are <ref group=note>
tags on this page, but the references will not show without a {{reflist|group=note}}
template (see the help page).
© MMXXIII Rich X Search. We shall prevail. All rights reserved. Rich X Search