Just war theory

Saint Augustine was the first clear advocate of just-war theory.

The just war theory (Latin: bellum iustum)[1][2] is a doctrine, also referred to as a tradition, of military ethics that aims to ensure that a war is morally justifiable through a series of criteria, all of which must be met for a war to be considered just. It has been studied by military leaders, theologians, ethicists and policymakers. The criteria are split into two groups: jus ad bellum ("right to go to war") and jus in bello ("right conduct in war"). The first group of criteria concerns the morality of going to war, and the second group of criteria concerns the moral conduct within war.[3] There have been calls for the inclusion of a third category of just war theory (jus post bellum) dealing with the morality of post-war settlement and reconstruction. The just war theory postulates the belief that war, while it is terrible but less so with the right conduct, is not always the worst option. Important responsibilities, undesirable outcomes, or preventable atrocities may justify war.[3]

Opponents of the just war theory may either be inclined to a stricter pacifist standard (proposing that there has never been nor can there ever be a justifiable basis for war) or they may be inclined toward a more permissive nationalist standard (proposing that a war need only to serve a nation's interests to be justifiable). In many cases, philosophers state that individuals do not need to be plagued by a guilty conscience if they are required to fight. A few philosophers ennoble the virtues of the soldier while they also declare their apprehensions for war itself.[4] A few, such as Rousseau, argue for insurrection against oppressive rule.

The historical aspect, or the "just war tradition", deals with the historical body of rules or agreements that have applied in various wars across the ages. The just war tradition also considers the writings of various philosophers and lawyers through history, and examines both their philosophical visions of war's ethical limits and whether their thoughts have contributed to the body of conventions that have evolved to guide war and warfare.[5]

In the twenty-first century there has been significant debate between traditional just war theorists, who largely support the existing law of war and develop arguments to support it, and revisionists who reject many traditional assumptions, although not necessarily advocating a change in the law.[6][7]

  1. ^ Cicero, Marcus Tullius; Miller, Walter (1913). De officiis. With an English translation by Walter Miller. Robarts - University of Toronto. London Heinemann.
  2. ^ Fellmeth, Aaron X.; Horwitz, Maurice (2009). "Bellum iustum". Guide to Latin in International Law. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acref/9780195369380.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-19-536938-0. Retrieved 27 February 2022.
  3. ^ a b Guthrie, Charles; Quinlan, Michael (2007). "III: The Structure of the Tradition". Just War: The Just War Tradition: Ethics in Modern Warfare. Bloomsbury. pp. 11–15. ISBN 978-0747595571.
  4. ^ McHenry, Robert (22 March 2010). "William James on Peace and War". blogs.britannica.com. Britannica Blog. Archived from the original on 31 October 2015. Retrieved 6 August 2017.
  5. ^ "Just War Theory". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 30 October 2016.
  6. ^ Lazar, Seth (2017). "Just War Theory: Revisionists Versus Traditionalists". Annual Review of Political Science. 20 (1): 37–54. doi:10.1146/annurev-polisci-060314-112706.
  7. ^ Lazar, Seth (2020). "War". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 13 June 2023.

© MMXXIII Rich X Search. We shall prevail. All rights reserved. Rich X Search